Reading Responses(Less Than 1 Page) 2 reading responses, each of them will only be one paragraph Global Environment and International Inequality Aut

Reading Responses(Less Than 1 Page)
2 reading responses, each of them will only be one paragraph

Global Environment and International Inequality
Author(s): Henry Shue
Source: International Affairs (Royal Institute of International Affairs 1944-), Vol. 75, No.
3 (Jul., 1999), pp. 531-545
Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Royal Institute of International
Affairs
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2623635
Accessed: 10-03-2020 16:08 UTC

Don't use plagiarized sources. Get Your Custom Assignment on
Reading Responses(Less Than 1 Page) 2 reading responses, each of them will only be one paragraph Global Environment and International Inequality Aut
From as Little as $13/Page

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide

range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and

facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [emailprotected]

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Terms and Conditions of Use

Royal Institute of International Affairs, Oxford University Press are collaborating with
JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to International Affairs (Royal Institute of
International Affairs 1944-)

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Global environment and international

inequality

HENRY SHUE

My aim is to establish that three commonsense principles of fairness, none of

them dependent upon controversial philosophical theories ofjustice, give rise to

the same conclusion about the allocation of the costs of protecting the environ-

ment.

Poor states and rich states have long dealt with each other primarily upon

unequal terms. The imposition of unequal terms has been relatively easy for the

rich states because they have rarely needed to ask for the voluntary cooperation

of the less powerful poor states. Now the rich countries have realized that their

own industrial activity has been destroying the ozone in the earth’s atmosphere

and has been making far and away the greatest contribution to global warming.

They would like the poor states to avoid adopting the same form of industriali-

zation by which they themselves became rich. It is increasingly clear that if poor

states pursue their own economic development with the same disregard for the

natural environment and the economic welfare of other states that rich states

displayed in the past during their development, everyone will continue to suffer

the effects of environmental destruction. Consequently, it is at least conceivable

that rich states might now be willing to consider dealing cooperatively on

equitable terms with poor states in a manner that gives due weight to both the

economic development of poor states and the preservation of the natural

environment.

If we are to have any hope of pursuing equitable cooperation, we must try to

arrive at a consensus about what equity means. And we need to define equity,

not as a vague abstraction, but concretely and specifically in the context of both

development of the economy in poor states and preservation of the environ-

ment everywhere.

Fundamental fairness and acceptable inequality

What diplomats and lawyers call equity incorporates important aspects of what

ordinary people everywhere call fairness. The concept of fairness is neither

International Affairs 75, 3 (I999) 531I-545 5 3I

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Henry Shue

Eastern nor Western, Northern nor Southern, but universal.’ People every-

where understand what it means to ask whether an arrangement is fair or biased

towards some parties over other parties. If you own the land but I supply the

labour, or you own the seed but I own the ox, or you are old but I am young,

or you are female but I am male, or you have an education and I do not, or you

worked long and hard but I was lazy-in situation after situation it makes

perfectly good sense to ask whether a particular division of something among

two or more parties is fair to all the parties, in light of this or that difference

between them. All people understand the question, even where they have been

taught not to ask it. What would be fair? Or, as the lawyers and diplomats

would put it, which arrangement would be equitable?

Naturally, it is also possible to ask other kinds of questions about the same

arrangements. One can always ask economic questions, for instance, in addition

to ethical questions concerning equity: would it increase total output if, say,
women were paid less and men were paid more? Would it be more efficient?

Sometimes the most efficient arrangement happens also to be fair to all parties,

but often it is unfair. Then a choice has to be made between efficiency and fair-

ness. Before it is possible to discuss such choices, however, we need to know

the meaning of equity: what are the standards of equity and how do they matter?

Complete egalitarianism-the belief that all good things ought to be shared

equally among all people-can be a powerfully attractive view, and it is much

more difficult to argue against than many of its opponents seem to think. I shall,

nevertheless, assume here that complete egalitarianism is unacceptable. If it

were the appropriate view to adopt, our inquiry into equity could end now.

The answer to the question, ‘what is an equitable arrangement?’ would always

be the same: an equal distribution. Only equality would ever provide equity.

While I do assume that it may be equitable for some good things to be
distributed unequally, I also assume that other things must be kept equal-most

importantly, dignity and respect. It is part of the current international consensus

that every person is entitled to equal dignity and equal respect. In traditional

societies in both hemispheres, even the equality of dignity and respect was

denied in theory as well as practice. Now, although principles of equality are

still widely violated in practice, inequality of dignity and of respect have

relatively few public advocates even among those who practice them. If it is

equitable for some other human goods to be distributed unequally, but it is not

equitable for dignity or respect to be unequal, the central questions become:

‘which inequalities in which other human goods are compatible with equal

human dignity and equal human respect?’ and ‘which inequalities in other

goods ought to be eliminated, reduced or prevented from being increased?’

When one is beginning from an existing inequality, like the current inequality

in wealth between North and South, three critical kinds of justification are:

Or so I believe. I would be intensely interested in any evidence of a culture that seems to lack a concept
of fairness, as distinguished from evidence about two cultures whose specific conceptions of fairness differ
in some respects.

532

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Global environment and international inequality

justifications of unequal burdens intended to reduce or eliminate the existing

inequality by removing an unfair advantage of those at the top; justifications of

unequal burdens intended to prevent the existing inequality from becoming

worse through any infliction of an unfair additional disadvantage upon those at

the bottom; and justifications of a guaranteed minimum intended to prevent the

existing inequality from becoming worse through any infliction of an unfair

additional disadvantage upon those at the bottom. The second justification for

unequal burdens and the justification for a guaranteed minimum are the same:

two different mechanisms are being used to achieve fundamentally the same

purpose. I shall look at these two forms of justification for unequal burdens and

then at the justification for a guaranteed minimum.

Unequal burdens

Greater contribution to the problem

All over the world parents teach their children to clean up their own mess. This

simple rule makes good sense from the point of view of incentive: if one learns

that one will not be allowed to get away with simply walking away from what-

ever messes one creates, one is given a strong negative incentive against making

messes in the first place. Whoever makes the mess presumably does so in the

process of pursuing some benefit-for a child, the benefit may simply be the

pleasure of playing with the objects that constitute the mess. If one learns that

whoever reaps the benefit of making the mess must also be the one who pays
the cost of cleaning up the mess, one learns at the very least not to make messes

with costs that are greater than their benefits.

Economists have glorified this simple rule as the ‘internalization of extern-

alities’. If the basis for the price of a product does not incorporate the costs of

cleaning up the mess made in the process of producing the product, the costs are

being externalized, that is, dumped upon other parties. Incorporating into the

basis of the price of the product the costs that had been coercively socialized is

called internalizing an externality.

At least as important as the consideration of incentives, however, is the

consideration of fairness or equity. If whoever makes a mess receives the bene-

fits and does not pay the costs, not only does he have no incentive to avoid

making as many messes as he likes, but he is also unfair to whoever does pay the

costs. He is inflicting costs upon other people, contrary to their interests and,

presumably, without their consent. By making himself better off in ways that

make others worse off, he is creating an expanding inequality.
Once such an inequality has been created unilaterally by someone’s imposing

costs upon other people, we are justified in reversing the inequality by imposing

extra burdens upon the producer of the inequality. There are two separate

points here. First, we are justified in assigning additional burdens to the party

who has been inflicting costs upon us. Second, the minimum extent of the

533

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Henry Shue

compensatory burden we are justified in assigning is enough to correct the

inequality previously unilaterally imposed. The purpose of the extra burden is

to restore an equality that was disrupted unilaterally and arbitrarily (or to reduce

an inequality that was enlarged unilaterally and arbitrarily). In order to accom-

plish that purpose, the extra burden assigned must be at least equal to the unfair

advantage previously taken. This yields us our first principle of equity:

When a party has in the past taken an unfair advantage of others by imposing costs upon

them without their consent, those who have been unilaterally put at a disadvantage are

entitled to demand that in the future the offending party shoulder burdens that are

unequal at least to the extent of the unfair advantage previously taken, in order to

restore equality.2

In the area of development and the environment, the clearest cases that fall

under this first principle of equity are the partial destruction of the ozone layer

and the initiation of global warming by the process of industrialization that has

enriched the North but not the South. Unilateral initiatives by the so-called

developed countries (DCs) have made them rich, while leaving the less

developed countries (LDCs) poor. In the process the industrial activities and

accompanying lifestyles of the DCs have inflicted major global damage upon

the earth’s atmosphere. Both kinds of damage are harmful to those who did not

benefit from Northern industrialization as well as to those who did. Those

societies whose activities have damaged the atmosphere ought, according to the

first principle of equity, to bear sufficiently unequal burdens henceforth to

correct the inequality that they have imposed. In this case, everyone is bearing

costs-because the damage was universal-but the benefits have been over-

whelmingly skewed towards those who have become rich in the process.

This principle of equity should be distinguished from the considerably

weaker-because entirely forward-looking-‘polluter pays principle’ (PPP),

which requires only that all future costs of pollution (in production or

consumption) be henceforth internalized into prices. Even the OECD formally

adopted the PPP in I974, to govern relations among rich states.3

Spokespeople for the rich countries make at least three kinds of counter-

arguments to this first principle of equity. These are:

i. The LDCs have also benefited, it is said, from the enrichment of the

DCs. Usually it is conceded that the industrial countries have benefited more

than the non-industrialized. Yet it is maintained that, for example, medicines

and technologies made possible by the lifestyles of the rich countries have also

reached the poor countries, bringing benefits that the poor countries could not

have produced as soon for themselves.

2 A preliminary presentation of these principles at New York University Law School has been helpfully
commented upon in Thomas M. Franck, Fairness in international law and institutions (Oxford: Clarendon,
I997), pp. 390-9I.

3 OECD Council, I4 November I974C (I974), 223 (Paris: OECD, I974).

534

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Global environment and international inequality

Quite a bit of breath and ink has been spent in arguments over how much

LDCs have benefited from the technologies and other advances made by the

DCs, compared to the benefits enjoyed by the DCs themselves. Yet this dispute

does not need to be settled in order to decide questions of equity. Whatever

benefits LDCs have received, they have mostly been charged for. No doubt

some improvements have been widespread. Yet, except for a relative trickle of

aid, all transfers have been charged to the recipients, who have in fact been left

with an enormous burden of debt, much of it incurred precisely in the effort to

purchase the good things produced by industrialization.

Overall, poor countries have been charged for any benefits that they have

received by someone in the rich countries, evening that account. Much greater

additional benefits have gone to the rich countries themselves, including a

major contribution to the very process of their becoming so much richer than

the poor countries. Meanwhile, the environmental damage caused by the

process has been incurred by everyone. The rich countries have profited to the

extent of the excess of the benefits gained by them over the costs incurred by

everyone through environmental damage done by them, and ought in future to

bear extra burdens in dealing with the damage they have done.

2. Whatever environmental damage has been done, it is said, was uninten-

tional. Now we know all sorts of things about CFCs and the ozone layer, and

about carbon dioxide and the greenhouse effect, that no one dreamed of when

CFCs were created or when industrialization fed with fossil fuels began. People

cannot be held responsible, it is maintained, for harmful effects that they could

not have foreseen. The philosopher Immanuel Kant is often quoted in the West

for having said, ‘Ought presupposes can’-it can be true that one ought to have

done something only if one actually could have done it. Therefore, it is

allegedly not fair to hold people responsible for effects they could not have

avoided because the effects could not have been predicted.

This objection rests upon a confusion between punishment and respon-

sibility. It is not fair to punish somneone for producing effects that could not
have been avoided, but it is common to hold people responsible for effects that

were unforeseen and unavoidable.

We noted earlier that, in order to be justifiable, an inequality in something

between two or more parties must be compatible with an equality of dignity

and respect between the parties. If there were an inequality between two groups

of people such that members of the first group could create problems and then

expect members of the second group to deal with the problems, that inequality

would be incompatible with equal respect and equal dignity. For the members

of the second group would in fact be functioning as servants for the first group.

If I said to you, ‘I broke it, but I want you to clean it up’, then I would be your

master and you would be my servant. If I thought that you should do my

bidding, I could hardly respect you as my equal.

It is true, then, that the owners of many coal-burning factories could not

possibly have known the bad effects of the carbon dioxide they were releasing

535

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Henry Shue

into the atmosphere, and therefore could not possibly have intended to contri-

bute to harming it. It would, therefore, be unfair to punish them-by, for

example, demanding that they pay double or triple damages. It is not in the least

unfair, however, simply to hold them responsible for the damage that they have

in fact done. This naturally leads to the third objection.

3. Even if it is fair to hold a person responsible for damage done uninten-

tionally, it will be said, it is not fair to hold the person responsible for damage he

did not do himself. It would not be fair, for example, to hold a grandson

responsible for damage done by his grandfather. Yet it is claimed this is exactly

what is being done when the current generation is held responsible for carbon

dioxide emissions produced in the nineteenth century. Perhaps Europeans

living today are responsible for atmosphere-damaging gases ermitted today, but

it is not fair to hold people responsible for deeds done long before they were

born.

This objection appeals to a reasonable principle, namely that one person

ought not to be held responsible for what is done by another person who is

completely unrelated. ‘Completely unrelated’ is, however, a critical portion of

the principle. To assume that the facts about the industrial North’s contribution

to global warming straightforwardly fall under this principle is to assume that

they are considerably simpler than they actually are.

First, and undeniably, the industrial states’ contributions to global warming

have continued unabated long since it became impossible to plead ignorance. It

would have been conceivable that as soon as evidence began to accumulate that

industrial activity was having a dangerous environmental effect, the industrial

states would have adopted a conservative or even cautious policy of cutting

back greenhouse-gas emissions or at least slowing their rate of increase. For the

most part this has not happened.

Second, today’s generation in the industrial states is far from completely

unrelated to the earlier generations going back all the way to the beginning of

the Industrial Revolution. What is tlhe difference between being born in I975

in Belgium and being born in I975 in Bangladesh? Clearly one of the most
fundamental differences is that the Belgian infant is born into an industrial

society and the Bangladeshi infant is not. Even the medical setting for the birth

itself, not to mention the level of prenatal care available to the expectant
mother, is almost certainly vastly more favourable for the Belgian than the

Bangladeshi. Childhood nutrition, educational opportunities and life-long

standards of living are likely to differ enormously because of the difference

between an industrialized and a non-industrialized economy. In such respects

current generations are, and future generations probably will be, continuing

beneficiaries of earlier industrial activity.

Nothing is wrong with the principle invoked in the third objection. It is

indeed not fair to hold someone responsible for what has been done by

someone else. Yet that principle is largely irrelevant to the case at hand, because
one generation of a rich industrial society is not unrelated to other generations

536

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Global environment and international inequality

past and future. All are participants in enduring economriic structures. Benefits
and costs, and rights and responsibilities, carry across generations.

We turn now to a second, quite different kind of justification of the same

mechanism of assigning unequal burdens. This first justification has rested in

part upon the unfairness of the existing inequality. The second justification
neither assumes nor argues that the initial inequality is unfair.

Greater ability to pay

The second principle of equity is widely accepted as a requirement of simple

fairness. It states:

Among a number of parties, all of whom are bound to contribute to some common

endeavour, the parties who have the most resources normally should contribute the

most to the endeavour.

This principle of paying in accordance with ability to pay, if stated strictly,
would specify what is often called a progressive rate of payment: insofar as a

party’s assets are greater, the rate at which the party should contribute to the

enterprise in question also becomes greater. The progressivity can be strictly

proportional-those with double the base amount of assets contribute at

twice the rate at which those with the base amount contribute, those with

triple the base amount of assets contribute at three times the rate at which

those with the base amount contribute, and so on. More typically, the
progressivity is not strictly proportional-the more a party has, the higher the
rate at which it is expected to contribute, but the rate does not increase in

strict proportion to increases in assets.

The general principle itself is sufficiently fundamental that it is not

necessary, and perhaps not possible, to justify it by deriving it from con-
siderations that are more fundamental still. Nevertheless, it is possible to

explain its appeal to some extent more fully. The basic appeal of payment in

accordance with ability to pay as a principle of fairness is easiest to see by

contrast with a flat rate of contribution, that is, the same rate of contribution

by every party irrespective of different parties’ differing assets. At first
thought, the same rate for everyone seems obviously the fairest imaginable

arrangement. What could possibly be fairer, one is initially inclined to think,

than absolutely equal treatment for everyone? Surely, it seems, if everyone

pays an equal rate, everyone is treated the same and therefore fairly? This,
however, is an exceedingly abstract approach, which pays no attention at all
to the actual concrete circumstances of the contributing parties. In addition, it

focuses exclusively upon the contribution process and ignores the position in

which, as a result of the process, the parties end up. Contribution according
to ability to pay is much more sensitive both to concrete circumstance and to

final outcome.

S37

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Henry Shue

Suppose that Party A has go units of something, Party B has 30 units, and
Party C has 9 units. In order to accomplish their missions, it is proposed that
everyone should contribute at a flat rate of one-third. This may seem fair in that

everyone is treated equally: the same rate is applied to everyone, regardless of

circumstances. When it is considered that A’s contribution will be 30 and B’s

will be io, while C’s will be only 3, the flat rate may appear more than fair to C

who contributes only one-tenth as much as A does. However, suppose that

these units represent $ioo per year in income and that where C lives it is

possible to survive on $750 per year but on no less. If C must contribute 3

units-$3oo-he will fall below the minimum for survival. While the flat rate

of one-third would require A to contribute far more ($3 ,ooo) than C, and B to
contribute considerably more ($i,ooo) than C, both A (with $6,ooo left) and B
(with $2,000 left) would remain safely above subsistence level. A and B can

afford to contribute at the rate of one-third because they are left with more than

enough while C is unable to contribute at that rate and survive.

While flat rates appear misleadingly fair in the abstract, they do so largely

because they look at only the first part of the story and ignore how things turn

out in the end. The great strength of progressive rates, by contrast, is that they

tend to accommodate final outcomes and take account of whether the

contributors can in fact afford their respective contributions.

A single objection is usually raised against progressive rates of contribution:

disincentive effects. If those who have more are going to lose what they have at

a greater rate than those who have less, the incentive to come to have more in

the first place will, it is said, be much less than it would have been with a flat rate

of contribution. Why should I take more risks, display more imagination, or

expend more effort in order to gain more resources if the result will only be

that, whenever something must be paid for, I will have to contribute not merely

a larger absolute amount (which would happen even with a flat rate) but a larger

percentage? I might as well not be productive if much of anything extra I

produce will be taken away from me, leaving me little better off than those who

produced far less.

Three points need to be noticed regarding this objection. First, of course,

being fair and providing incentives are two different matters, and there is

certainly no guarantee in the abstract that whatever arrangement would provide

the greatest incentives would also be fair.

Second, concerns about incentives often arise when it is assumed that maximum

production and limitless growth are the best goal. It is increasingly clear that

many current forms of production and growth are unsustainable and that the last

thing we should do is to give people self-interested reasons to consume as many

resources as they can, even where the resources are consumed productively. These

issues cannot be settled in the abstract either, but it is certainly an open question-

and one that should be asked very seriously-whether in a particular situation it
is desirable to stimulate people by means of incentives to maximum production.

Sometimes it is desirable, and sometimes it is not. This is an issue about ends.

538

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Global environment and international inequality

Third, there is a question about means. Assuming that it had been demon-

strated that the best goal to have in a specific set of circumstances involved

stimulating more production of something, one would then have to ask: how

much incentive is needed to stimulate that much production? Those who are

preoccupied with incentives often speculate groundlessly that unlimited

incentives are virtually always required. Certainly it is true that it is generally

necessary to provide some additional incentive in order to stimulate additional

production. Some people are altruistic and are therefore sometimes willing to

contribute more to the welfare of others even if they do not thereby improve

their own welfare. It would be completely unrealistic, however, to try to

operate an economy on the assumption that people generally would produce

more irrespective of whether doing so was in their own interest-they need

instead to be provided with some incentive. However, some incentive does not

mean unlimited incentive.

It is certainly not necessary to offer unlimited incentives in order to stimulate

(limited) additional production by some people (and not others). Whether people

respond or not depends upon individual personalities and individual circum-

stances. It is a factual matter, not something to be decreed in the abstract, how

much incentive is enough: for these people in these circumstances to produce

this much more, how much incentive is enough? What is clearly mistaken is the

frequent assumption that nothing less than the maximum incentive is ever

enough.

In conclusion, insofar as the objection based on disincentive effects is

intended to be a decisive refutation of the second principle of equity, the

objection fails. It is not always a mistake to offer less than the maximum possible

incentive, even when the goal of thereby increasing production has itself been

justified. There is no evidence that anything less than the maximum is even

generally a mistake. Psychological effects must be determined case by case.

On the other hand, the objection based on disincentive effects may be
intended-much more modestly-simply as a warning that one of the possible

costs of restraining inequalities by means of progressive rates of contribution, in

the effort of being fair, may (or may not) be a reduction in incentive effects. As

a caution rather than a (failed) refutation, the objection points to one sensible

consideration that needs to be taken into account when specifying which

variation upon the general second principle of equity is the best version to adopt

in a specific case. One would have to consider how much greater the incentive

effect would be if the rate of contribution were less progressive, in light of how

unfair the results of a less progressive rate would be.

This conclusion that disincentive effects deserve to be considered, although

they are not always decisive, partly explains why the second principle of equity

is stated, not as an absolute, but as a general principle. It says: ‘… the parties who

have the most resources normally should contribute the most…’-not always,

but normally. One reason why the rate of contribution might not be progress-
ive, or might not be as progressive as possible, is the potential disincentive

539

This content downloaded from 169.234.207.80 on Tue, 10 Mar 2020 16:08:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Henry Shue

effects of more progressive rates. It would need to be shown case by case that an

important goal was served by having some incentive and that the goal in

question would not be served by the weaker incentive compatible with a more

progressive rate of contribution.

We have so far examined two quite different kinds ofjustifications of unequal

burdens: to reduce or eliminate an existing inequality by removing an unfair

advantage of those at the top and to prevent the existing inequality from

becoming worse through any infliction of an unfair additional disadvantage

upon those at the bottom. The first justification rests in part upon explaining why

the initial inequality is unfair and ought to be removed or reduced. The second

justification applies irrespective of whether the initial inequality is fair. Now we

turn to a different mechanism that-much more directly-serves the second

purpose of avoiding making those who are already the worst-off yet worse off.

Guaranteed minimum

We noted earlier that issues of equity or fairness can arise only if there is some-

thing that must be divided among different parties. The existence of the

following circumstances can be taken as grounds for thinking that certain parties

have a legitimate claim to some of the available resources: (a) the aggregate total

of resources is sufficient for all parties to have more than enough; (b) some

parties do in fact have more than enough, some of them much more than

enough; and (c) other parties have less than enough. American philosopher

Thomas Nagel has called such circumstances radical inequality.4 Such an

inequality is radical in part because the total of available r